Thursday, 19 November 2015

Can there ever be aa all embracing Moral Theory?




What is a moral theory? Bernard Williams’ characterisation gives us a first

approximation: “a philosophical structure which, together with some degree of

empirical fact, will yield a decision procedure for moral reasoning”.( William 1985,

p13) The clearest examples are the systematic normative theories that are

considered and compared in ethics are consequentialism, virtue ethics,

contractualism, Kantianism and natural law ethics.


Every “moral theory” in the tight sense—every first-order system of normative

practical philosophy—aspires to be an ethical outlook. It is not clear what point there

would be to a moral theory that did not have this aspiration. But there are problems

about supposing that any moral theory could adequately play the role that we want,

and need, our ethical outlook to encompass. (Thompson 1994 p 56)


Some of the reasons why this is so begin to appear when we note the intimate

connections that an adequate ethical outlook will inevitably have with motivation and

deliberation on the one hand, and explanation and prediction on the other. We want

our ethical outlook to be something which, in real time, can be the source of our

reasons to act (motivation), and which can structure our thinking and deciding about

how to act as it actually happens (deliberation). We also want our ethical outlook to

be something which, can articulate and deepen our understanding of what

counts as good or bad and right or wrong action, and why (explanation); and we

want it to be something which can explain what will or would be good or bad and

right or wrong action, in future or hypothetical situations that we ourselves have not

actually met, but which we or others might conceivably meet (prediction). (Thompson

1994 p 65 -75)


Moral theory is ill-fitted for any of these four roles. To see why, let us consider

them one by one. I have argued above that “we want our ethical outlook to be

something which can, itself, be the source of our reasons to act.” At a first look, it

seems that consequentialism identifies The Overall Good as the thing for good

people to be motivated by; that Kantianism’s motivational goal is rational action, in a

special sense of “rational”, or Duty, in a special sense of “Duty”; that virtue ethics

tells us to act out of the virtues; and so on. Perhaps some moral theorists in these

schools do think about motivation in this direct way: Peter Singer, for example,

seems more than once to suggest that we really should aim to be motivated by “the

overall good”; that there is nothing better to be motivated by, because there is

nothing bigger;

: “If we take the point of view of the universe we can recognise the urgency of doing
something about the pain and suffering of others, before we even consider promoting other possible
values...” Singer 1995, 276:




But this is not the line about what should motivate us among moral theorists, and

the reason why is obvious: the sheer implausibility of the moral theories’ adopting

any such direct account of motivation. As Wolf pointed out:

There is something odd about the idea of morality itself, or moral goodness,
serving as the object of a dominant passion in the way that a more concrete
and specific vision of a goal (even a concrete moral goal) might be imagined
to serve… when one reflects, for example, on the… Saint… giving up his
fishing trip or his stereo or his hot fudge sundae at the drop of the moral hat,
one is apt to wonder not at how much he loves morality, but at how little he
loves these other things. “(Wolf 1997, 83)

We want our ethical outlook to be one which can structure our thinking and

deciding about how to act as it actually happens. It is difficult to imagine a really

clean separation between questions about motivation, what moves us to act, and

about deliberation, our reasoning about how to act. For anyone, reasoning about

how to act will be an integral part of being moved to act, and vice versa. So doubts

about the place of moral theory in motivation are also, mutatis mutandis, doubts

about the place of moral theory in deliberation. If Utility or Duty or Virtue cannot

plausibly be the main spring of our motivation, then it cannot plausibly be central to

our deliberation either. It is no more plausible to say that a psychologically healthy

moral agent’s deliberations are typically guided by the question “What would

maximise utility?” than it is to say that she typically acts on the motive of maximising

utility.

Moral theorists will talk about moral theory as providing a constraint on

deliberation, or the form of deliberation, rather than the subject-matter or content of

deliberation. Deliberation, they argue , may take as its subject-matter whatever

desires motivate us, but it must always pass the universalisability test, or must

always be maximising deliberation, or must never be contrary to the rules laid down

by the virtues—and so on.

The first thing to say about this manoeuvre is just to point out that this too is a

retreat from our expectations of an ethical outlook, which, we might hope, will

provide both the content and the form of our deliberation. We would be justifiably

disappointed in an ethical outlook that was topic-neutral in the familiar way that

Humean and Hobbesian moral theories are: one that had nothing to say about what

We desired, and told us only how to pursue it. (Thompson

1994 p 85)


It is unrealistic to hope that moral theory will give us even the form of deliberation,

never mind both the form and the content. There is simply no reason to think that all

good deliberation must be universalisable or in accord with the virtues, or that it must

satisfy such supposed rules of rationality as a maximising rule. Theorists’ attempts to

argue the contrary are always vulnerable to the question posed by Williams “by what

right they legislate to the moral sentiments”. Of course good deliberation sometimes

calls upon considerations which look very like thoughts about universalisability or

utility or maximisation. But not always—and even when good deliberation does

deploy one of these thoughts in one context, that is no guarantee that it must deploy

that same thought in every other context. As soon as we look in detail at actual good

agents actually deliberating, the idea that any moral theory even gives the form of

their deliberations becomes hopelessly implausible. Good deliberation simply isn’t

that “programmed”.

It becomes implausible to think that good agents who are deliberating must be

explicitly and consciously using some moral theory as a constraint on that

deliberation. It may be that moral theory serve as a universal constraint on their

deliberation? That is to say: can’t deliberations in fact be always responsive to

such a constraint even if that constraint is not always a conscious part of their actual

thoughts in real-time moral reasoning—part of their “decision procedure”?

We want our ethical outlook to be something which can articulate and deepen our

understanding of what counts as good or bad and right or wrong action, and why.”

We might have expected moral theories to be on home ground here. After all,

explanation and prediction are supposed to be the main strength of sophisticated

moral theories. Those moral theorists who admit that moral theory cannot plausibly

be directly involved in motivation and deliberation see its main role, instead, in

explaining why it is good for agents to be motivate, and to deliberate, in whatever

way it is that their theory recommends.


One case where moral theory creates problems is a supposed difficulty about

punishment. When someone is punished for a crime, the crime has already

happened, and now the punishment is proposed as a way of dealing with it. But, the

objection runs (it is an old one: it goes back at least as far as Plato’s Protagoras),

how can it be good to make two bad things happen instead of just one? The heart of

this “problem” about punishment is the theory-driven assumption that all reasons

must be future-directed—that wherever there is a reason to act, it is because there is

some future state of affairs that can be brought about by so acting
.

Consequentialist moral theorists, for instance, have tended, in line with their general

and characteristic preoccupation with the future, to suggest that the wrongness of

murder lies in something like its depriving its victim of a “future like ours” or a “future

life of value” (Marquis 2002). Such suggestions seem obviously false. Knowing that

some person’s future will be radically unlike “ours”, or drastically deprived of positive

value, falls well short of what we need to know in order to know not only that it is not

wrong for that person to die; not only that it is not wrong for someone to kill that

person; but also that it is not wrong for us to kill that person.

Kantians, meanwhile, are likely to speak of murder either as a nonuniversalisable

choice, or as a failure to respect someone as an “end in himself”, or both. Both these

descriptions too seem right, as far as they go. But appeal to universalisability begs

the question as to why murder might not be universalisable; (Thompson

1994 p 101) similarly, the contractualist appeal to “the reasonably rejectable” begs

the question why murder might be reasonably rejected . As for failure to respect an

end in himself, this description does not explain why murder involves such a failure.

And here too the key notions of “respect” and of “ends in themselves” get more

complicated the more closely one looks at them; here too it would be nice to be able

to explain something that seems relatively simple and basic, the wrongness of

murder,without having to make the “detour through theory” that obliges us to thrash

out an account of these very difficult and obscure notions.

We want our ethical outlook “to explain what will or would be good or bad and right

or wrong action, in future or hypothetical situations that we ourselves have not

actually met, but which we or others might conceivably meet”. Prediction is, of

course, just the future or hypothetical correlate of explanation. Still, it is worth

considering separately, because thinking about prediction brings out more clearly

some difficulties for moral theory which are already latent in the notion of

explanation.

Moral theory’s difficulty about prediction is basically a problem of overambition.

What the moral theorist wants to say is that hypothetical case A would

inevitably be a case of right action (or wrong action, or good or bad action, or

whatever) because case A is just like real case B, which is right action: or again, that

cases A and B both fall under moral type T, and every instance of type T is a case of

right action.

The problem here is not restricted to the cases, common though they are,

where moral theorists expect us to produce clear and definite intuitions about

hypothetical cases which are very complicated, or very unlikely, or both. The trouble

is completely general, and it begins with the “inevitably”. As moral theorists

frequently point out, it is a requirement of rationality that the same moral verdict must

be returned on two qualitatively indiscernible cases. Of course. The only problem is

that there are no qualitatively indiscernible cases—not even in everyday life, never

mind in trolley or reduplicated human-shield problems. There are only cases which

are more or less roughly similar. Judgements about which similarities and which

differences matter, and how much, and why, and which exceptions override which

similarities, and how often, and why, can certainly be made. But the idea that there is

any set of similarity-judgements which is rationally required of us is simply a myth.

Picking up a similarity-judgement between two cases as the one that matters morally

is not a matter of pure reason or value-neutral logic; it is itself an exercise of moral

perception. So here the point is not exactly that non-theoretical ethical outlooks do

better at prediction than moral theories. Rather, it is that moral theories have an

overambitious explanatory pretension that they cannot possibly sustain, because it

rests on the false assumption that some pattern or other of similarity-judgements is

rationally required, and that anyone who fails to judge in line with this pattern is

cognitively deficient.


To sum up: most moral theories fail to fill the deliberative and motivational roles

that we want our ethical outlook to play—as the most moral theorists themselves

agree. And the explanations that moral theory offers of good and bad, rightness and

wrongness, typically do not articulate or deepen our understanding of those notions,

as a good ethical outlook does: where moral theory’s explanations are not clearly

false or frustratingly incomplete, they are generally just unhelpfully obscure. In the

final role that we want our ethical outlook to play, prediction of what will be right/

wrong// good/ bad in hypothetical cases, moral theory typically proves over-

ambitious: it tries to enforce a uniformity of similarity-judgements that simply cannot

be rationally required. In all these respects, typical moral theories fail the tests that

they need to pass to count as credible ethical outlooks in showing one theory better

than any other.



References

Marquis, D., “An argument that abortion is wrong” [2002]. In Hugh LaFollette (ed.),
Ethics in Practice. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 83-93.

Singer, P (1995). How Are We to Live?, Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.

Thomson , M (1994) Ethics , Hodder Education ,London

Williams, B.A.O. (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London:
Harmondsworth.

Wolf, S. “Moral Saints” [1997]. In Roger Crisp and Michael Slote (eds.), Virtue

Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.79-98.

No comments:

Post a Comment