Martin Heidegger (1889—1976)
Martin Heidegger is widely acknowledged to be one of the most original and important philosophers of the 20th century, while remaining one of the most controversial. His thinking has contributed to such diverse fields as phenomenology (Merleau-Ponty), existentialism (Sartre, Ortega y Gasset), hermeneutics (Gadamer, Ricoeur), political theory (Arendt, Marcuse, Habermas), psychology (Boss, Binswanger, Rollo May), and theology (Bultmann, Rahner, Tillich). His critique of traditional metaphysics and his opposition to positivism and technological world domination have been embraced by leading theorists of postmodernity (Derrida, Foucault, and Lyotard). On the other hand, his involvement in the Nazi movement has invoked a stormy debate. Although he never claimed that his philosophy was concerned with politics, political considerations have come to overshadow his philosophical work.
Heidegger’s main interest was ontology or the study of being. In his fundamental treatise, Being and Time,
he attempted to access being (Sein) by means of phenomenological
analysis of human existence (Dasein) in respect to its temporal and
historical character. After the change of his thinking (“the turn”),
Heidegger placed an emphasis on language as the vehicle through which
the question of being can be unfolded. He turned to the exegesis of
historical texts, especially of the Presocratics, but also of Kant,
Hegel, Nietzsche and Hölderlin, and to poetry, architecture, technology,
and other subjects. Instead of looking for a full clarification of the
meaning of being, he tried to pursue a kind of thinking which was no
longer “metaphysical.” He criticized the tradition of Western
philosophy, which he regarded as nihilistic, for, as he claimed, the
question of being as such was obliterated in it. He also stressed the
nihilism of modern technological culture. By going to the Presocratic
beginning of Western thought, he wanted to repeat the early Greek
experience of being, so that the West could turn away from the dead end
of nihilism and begin anew. His writings are notoriously difficult. Being and Time remains his most influential work.
Table of Contents
- Life and Works
- Philosophy as Phenomenological Ontology
- Dasein and Temporality
- The Quest for the Meaning of Being
- Overcoming Metaphysics
- From the First Beginning to the New Beginning
- From Philosophy to Political Theory
- Heidegger’s Collected Works
1. Life and Works
Heidegger was born on September 26, 1889 in Messkirch in south-west
Germany to a Catholic family. His father worked as sexton in the local
church. In his early youth, Heidegger was being prepared for the
priesthood. In 1903 he went to the high school in Konstanz, where the
church supported him with a scholarship, and then, in 1906, he moved to
Freiburg. His interest in philosophy first arose during his high school
studies in Freiburg when, at the age of seventeen, he read Franz
Brentano’s book entitled On the Manifold Meaning of Being according to Aristotle.
By his own account, it was this work that inspired his life-long quest
for the meaning of being. In 1909, after completing the high school, he
became a Jesuit novice, but was discharged within a month for reasons of
health. He then entered Freiburg University, where he studied theology.
However, because of health problems and perhaps because of a lack of a
strong spiritual vocation, Heidegger left the seminary in 1911 and broke
off his training for the priesthood. He took up studies in philosophy,
mathematics, and natural sciences. It was also at that time that he
first became influenced by Edmund Husserl. He studied Husserl's Logical Investigations. In 1913 he completed a doctorate in philosophy with a dissertation on The Doctrine of Judgement in Psychologism under the direction of the neo-Kantian philosopher Heinrich Rickert.
The outbreak of the First World War interrupted Heidegger’s academic
career only briefly. He was conscripted into the army, but was
discharged after two months because of health reasons. Hoping to take
over the chair of Catholic philosophy at Freiburg, Heidegger now began
to work on a habilitation thesis, the required qualification for teaching at the university. His thesis, Duns Scotus’s Doctrine of Categories and Meaning, was completed in 1915, and in the same year he was appointed a Privatdozent,
or lecturer. He taught mostly courses in Aristotelian and scholastic
philosophy, and regarded himself as standing in the service of the
Catholic world-view. Nevertheless, his turn from theology to philosophy
was soon to be followed by another turn.
In 1916, Heidegger became a junior colleague of Edmund Husserl when the
latter joined the Freiburg faculty. The following year, he married Thea
Elfride Petri, a Protestant student who had attended his courses since
the fall of 1915. His career was again interrupted by military service
in 1918. He served for the last ten months of the war, the last three of
those in a meteorological unit on the western front. Within a few weeks
of his return to Freiburg, he announced his break with the “system of
Catholicism” (January 9, 1919), got appointed as Husserl’s assistant
(January 21, 1919), and began lecturing in a new, insightful way
(February 7, 1919). His lectures on phenomenology and his creative
interpretations of Aristotle would now earn him a wide acclaim. And yet,
Heidegger did not simply become Husserl’s faithful follower. In
particular, he was not captivated by the later developments of Husserl’s
thought—by his neo-Kantian turn towards transcendental subjectivity and
even less by his Cartesianism—but continued to value his earlier work, Logical Investigations. Laboring over the question of things themselves, Heidegger soon began a radical reinterpretation of Husserl’s phenomenology.
In 1923, with the support of Paul Natorp, Heidegger was appointed
associate professor at Marburg University. Between 1923 and 1928, he
enjoyed there the most fruitful years of his entire teaching career. His
students testified to the originality of his insight and the intensity
of his philosophical questioning. Heidegger extended the scope of his
lectures, and taught courses on the history of philosophy, time, logic,
phenomenology, Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Kant, and Leibniz. However, he
had published nothing since 1916, a factor that threatened his future
academic career. Finally, in February 1927, partly because of
administrative pressure, his fundamental but also unfinished treatise, Being and Time, appeared. Within a few years, this book was recognized as a truly epoch-making work of 20th century
philosophy. It earned Heidegger, in the fall of 1927, full
professorship at Marburg, and one year later, after Husserl’s retirement
from teaching, the chair of philosophy at Freiburg University.
Although Being and Time is
dedicated to Husserl, upon its publication Heidegger’s departure from
Husserl’s phenomenology and the differences between two philosophers
became apparent. In 1929, his next published works—“What is
Metaphysics?,” “On the Essence of Ground,” and Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics—further
revealed how far Heidegger had moved from neo-Kantianism and
phenomenology of consciousness to his own phenomenological ontology.
Heidegger’s life entered a problematic and controversial stage with
Hitler’s rise to power. In September 1930, Adolf Hitler’s National
Socialist German Workers’ Party (NSDAP) became the second largest party
in Germany, and on January 30, 1933 Hitler was appointed chancellor of
Germany. Up to then virtually apolitical, Heidegger now became
politically involved. On April 21, 1933, he was elected rector of the
University of Freiburg by the faculty. He was apparently urged by his
colleagues to become a candidate for this politically sensitive post, as
he later claimed in an interview with Der Spiegel,
to avoid the danger of a party functionary being appointed. But he also
seemed to believe that he could steer the Nazi movement in the right
direction. On May 3, 1933, he joined the NSDAP, or Nazi, party. On May
27, 1933, he delivered his inaugural rectoral address on “The Self-Assertion of the German University.” The
ambiguous text of this speech has often been interpreted as an
expression of his support for Hitler’s regime. During his tenure as
rector he produced a number of speeches in the Nazi cause, such as, for
example, “Declaration of Support for Adolf Hitler and the National
Socialist State” delivered in November 1933. There is little doubt that
during that time, Heidegger placed the great prestige of his scholarly
reputation at the service of National Socialism, and thus, willingly or
not, contributed to its legitimization among his fellow Germans. And
yet, just one year later, on April 23, 1934, Heidegger resigned from his
office and took no further part in politics. His rectoral address was
found incompatible with the party line, and its text was eventually
banned by the Nazis. Because he was no longer involved in the party’s
activities, Heidegger’s membership in the NSDAP became a mere formality.
Certain restrictions were put on his freedom to publish and attend
conferences. In his lecture courses of the late 1930s and early 1940s,
and especially in the course entitled Hölderlin’s Hymnen “Germanien” und “Der Rein” (Hölderlin’s
Hymns “Germania” and “The Rhine”) originally presented at the
University of Freiburg during the winter semester of 1934/35, he
expressed covert criticism of Nazi ideology. He came under attack of
Ernst Krieck, semi-official Nazi philosopher. For some time he was under
the surveillance of the Gestapo. His final humiliation came in 1944,
when he was declared the most “expendable” member of the faculty and
sent to the Rhine to dig trenches. Following Germany’s defeat in the
Second World War, Heidegger was accused of Nazi sympathies. He was
forbidden to teach and in 1946 was dismissed from his chair of
philosophy. The ban was lifted in 1949.
The 1930s are not only marked by Heidegger’s controversial involvement
in politics, but also by a change in his thinking which is known as “the
turn” (die Kehre).
In his lectures and writings that followed “the turn,” he became less
systematic and often more obscure than in his fundamental work, Being and Time. He
turned to the exegesis of philosophical and literary texts, especially
of the Presocratics, but also of Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche and Hölderlin,
and makes this his way of philosophizing. A recurring theme of that time
was “the essence of truth.” During the decade between 1931 and 1940,
Heidegger offered five courses under this title. His preoccupation with
the question of language and his fascination with poetry were expressed
in lectures on Hörderlin which he gave between 1934 and 1936. Towards
the end of 1930s and the beginning of 1940s, he taught five courses on
Nietzsche, in which he submitted to criticism the tradition of western
metaphysics, described by him as nihilistic, and made allusions to the
absurdity of war and the bestiality of his contemporaries. Finally, his
reflection upon the western philosophical tradition and an endeavor to
open a space for philosophizing outside it, brought him to an
examination of Presocratic thought. In the course of lectures entitled An Introduction to Metaphysics,
which was originally offered as a course of lectures in 1935, and can
be seen as a bridge between earlier and later Heidegger, the
Presocratics were no longer a subject of mere passing remarks as in
Heidegger’s earlier works. The course was not about early Greek thought,
yet the Presocratics became there the pivotal center of discussion. It
is clear that with the evolution of Heidegger’s thinking in the 1930s,
they gained in importance in his work. During the 1940s, in addition to
giving courses on Aristotle, Kant and Hegel, Heidegger lectured
extensively on Anaximander, Parmenides, and Heraclitus.
During the last three decades of his life, from the mid 1940s to the mid
1970s, Heidegger wrote and published much, but in comparison to earlier
decades, there was no significant change in his philosophy. In his
insightful essays and lectures, such as “What are Poets for?” (1946),
“Letter on Humanism” (1947), “The Question Concerning Technology”
(1953), “The Way to Language” (1959), “Time and Being” (1962), and “The
End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking” (1964), he addressed
different issues concerning modernity, labored on his original
philosophy of history—the history of being—and attempted to clarify his
way of thinking after “the turn”. Most of his time was divided between
his home in Freiburg, his second study in Messkirch, and his mountain
hut in the Black Forest. But he escaped provincialism by being
frequently visited by his friends (including, among the others, the
political philosopher Hannah Arendt, the physicist Werner Heisenberg,
the theologian Rudolf Bultmann, the psychologist Ludwig Binswanger) and
by traveling more widely than ever before. He lectured on “What is
Philosophy?” at Cerisy-la-Salle in 1955, and on “Hegel and the Greeks”
at Aix-en-Provence in 1957, and also visited Greece in 1962 and 1967. In
1966, Heidegger attempted to justify his political involvement during
the Nazi regime in an interview with Der Spiegel entitled “Only God Can
Save Us”. One of his last teaching stints was a seminar on Parmenides
that he gave in Zähringen in 1973. Heiddegger died on May 26, 1976, and
was buried in the churchyard in Messkirch. He remained intellectually
active up until the very end, working on a number of projects, including
the massive Gesamtausgabe, the complete edition of his works.
2. Philosophy as Phenomenological Ontology
In order to understand Heidegger’s philosophy before “the turn”, let us
first briefly consider his indebtedness to Edmund Husserl. As it has
been mentioned, Heidegger was interested in Husserl from his early
student years at the University of Freiburg when he read Logical Investigations.
Later, when Husserl accepted a chair at Freiburg, Heidegger became his
assistant. His debt to Husserl cannot be overlooked. Not only is Being and Time dedicated
to Husserl, but also Heidegger acknowledges in it that without
Husserl’s phenomenology his own investigation would not have been
possible. How then is Heidegger’s philosophy related to the Husserlian
program of phenomenology?
By “phenomenology” Husserl himself had always meant the science of
consciousness and its objects; this core of sense pervades the
development of this concept as eidetic, transcendental or constructive
throughout his works. Following the Cartesian tradition, he saw the
ground and the absolute starting point of philosophy in the subject. The
procedure of bracketing is essential to Husserl’s “phenomenological
reduction”—the methodological procedure by which we are led from “the
natural attitude,” in which we are involved in the actual world and its
affairs, to “the phenomenological attitude,” in which the analysis and
detached description of the content of consciousness is possible. The
phenomenological reduction helps us to free ourselves from prejudices
and secure the purity of our detachment as observers, so that we can
encounter “things as they are in themselves” independently of any
presuppositions. The goal of phenomenology for Husserl is then a
descriptive, detached analysis of consciousness, in which objects, as
its correlates, are constituted.
What right does Husserl have to insist that the original mode of
encounter with beings, in which they appear to us as they are as things
in themselves, is the encounter of consciousness purified by
phenomenological reduction and its objects? “Whence and how is it
determined what must be experienced as the ‘things themselves’ in
accordance with the principle of phenomenology?” These are pressing
questions which Heidegger might well have asked. Perhaps because of his
reverence for Husserl, he does not subject him to direct criticism in
his fundamental work. Nevertheless,Being and Time is
itself a powerful critique of the Husserlian phenomenology. Heidegger
there gives attention to many different modes in which we exist and
encounter things. He analyses the structures constitutive of things not
only as they are encountered in the detached, theoretical attitude of
consciousness, but also in daily life as “utensils” (Zuhandene) or in special moods, especially in anxiety (Angst).
What is more, he exhibits there the structures that are constitutive of
the particular kind of being which is the human being and which he
calls “Dasein.” For Heidegger, it is not pure consciousness in which
beings are originally constituted. The starting point of philosophy for
him is not consciousness, but Dasein in its being.
The central problem for Husserl is the problem of constitution: How is
the world as phenomenon constituted in our consciousness? Heidegger
takes the Husserlian problem one step further. Instead of asking how
something must be given in consciousness in order to be constituted, he
asks: “What is the mode of being of that being in which the world
constitutes itself?” In a letter to Husserl dated October 27, 1927, he
states that the question of Dasein's being cannot be evaded, as far as
the problem of constitution is concerned. Dasein is that being in which
any being is constituted. Further, the question of Dasein's being
directs him to the problem of being in general. The “universal problem
of being,” he says in the same letter, “refers to that which constitutes
and to that which is constituted.” While far from being dependent upon
Husserl, Heidegger finds in his thought an inspiration leading him to
the theme which has continued to draw his attention since his early
years: the question of the meaning of being.
Phenomenology thus receives in Heidegger a new meaning. He conceives it
more broadly, and more etymologically, than Husserl, as “letting what
shows itself to be seen from itself, just as it shows from itself.”
Husserl applies the term “phenomenology” to a whole philosophy.
Heidegger takes it rather to designate a method. Since in Being and Time philosophy
is described as “ontology” and has being as its theme, it cannot adopt
its method from any of the actual sciences. For Heidegger the method of
ontology is phenomenology. “Phenomenology,” he says, “is the way of
access to what is to become the theme of ontology.” Being is to be
grasped by means of the phenomenological method. However, being is
always the being of a being, and accordingly, it becomes accessible only
indirectly through some existing entity. Therefore, “phenomenological
reduction” is necessary. One must direct oneself toward an entity, but
in such a way that its being is thereby brought out. It is Dasein which
Heidegger chooses as the particular entity to access being. Hence, as
the basic component of his phenomenology, Heidegger adopts the
Husserlian phenomenological reduction, but gives it a completely
different meaning.
To sum up, Heidegger does not base his philosophy on consciousness as
Husserl did. For him the phenomenological or theoretical attitude of
consciousness, which Husserl makes the core of his doctrine, is only one
possible mode of that which is more fundamental, namely, Dasein's
being. Although he agrees with Husserl that the transcendental
constitution of the world cannot be unveiled by naturalistic or physical
explanations, in his view it is not a descriptive analysis of
consciousness that leads to this end, but the analysis of Dasein.
Phenomenology for him is not a descriptive, detached analysis of
consciousness. It is a method of access to being. For the Heidegger of Being and Time, philosophy is phenomenological ontology which takes its departure from the analysis of Dasein.
3. Dasein and Temporality
In everyday German language the word “Dasein” means life or existence.
The noun is used by other German philosophers to denote the existence of
any entity. However, Heidegger breaks the word down to its components
“Da” and “Sein,” and gives to it a special meaning which is related to
his answer to the question of who the human being is. He relates this
question to the question of being. Dasein, that being which we ourselves
are, is distinguished from all other beings by the fact that it makes
issue of its own being. It stands out to being. As Da-sein, it is the
site, “Da”, for the disclosure of being, “Sein.”
Heidegger’s fundamental analysis of Dasein from Being and Time points
to temporality as the primordial meaning of Dasein’s being. Dasein is
essentially temporal. Its temporal character is derived from the
tripartite ontological structure: existence, thrownness, and fallenness by which Dasein’s being is described. Existence means that Dasein is potentiality-for-being (Seinkönnen);
it projects its being upon various possibilities. Existence represents
thus the phenomenon of the future. Then, as thrownness, Dasein always
finds itself already in a certain spiritual and material, historically
conditioned environment; in short, in the world, in which the space of
possibilities is always somehow limited. This represents the phenomenon
of the past as having-been. Finally, as fallenness, Dasein exists in the
midst of beings which are both Dasein and not Dasein. The encounter
with those beings, “being-alongside” or “being-with” them, is made
possible for Dasein by the presence of those beings within-the-world.
This represents the primordial phenomenon of the present. Accordingly,
Dasein is not temporal for the mere reason that it exists “in time,” but
because its very being is rooted in temporality: the original unity of
the future, the past and the present. Temporality cannot be identified
with ordinary clock time - with simply being at one point in time, at
one “Now” after another—which for Heidegger is a derivative phenomenon.
Neither does Dasein’s temporality have the merely quantitative,
homogeneous character of the concept of time found in natural science.
It is the phenomenon of original time, of the time which “temporalizes”
itself in the course of Dasein’s existence. It is a movement through a
world as a space of possibilities. The “going back” to the possibilities
that have been (the past) in the moment of thrownness, and their
projection in the resolute movement “coming towards” (the future) in the
moment of existence, which both take place in “being with” others (the
present) in the moment of fallenness, provide for the original unity of
the future, the past, and the present which constitutes authentic
temporality.
As authentically temporal, Dasein as potentiality-for-being comes
towards itself in its possibilities of being by going back to what has
been; it always comes towards itself from out of a possibility of
itself. Hence, it comports itself towards the future by always coming
back to its past; the past which is not merely past but still around as
having-been. But in this “going back” to what it has been which is
constitutive together with “coming towards” and “being with” for the
unity of Dasein’s temporality, Dasein hands down to itself its own
historical “heritage,” namely, the possibilities of being that have come
down to it. As authentically temporal, Dasein is thus authentically
historical. The repetition of the possibilities of existence, of that
which has been, is for Heidegger constitutive for the phenomenon of
original history which is rooted in temporality.
4. The Quest for the Meaning of Being
Throughout his long academic career, Heidegger was preoccupied with the
question of the meaning of being. His first formulation of this question
goes as far back as his high school studies, during which he read Franz
Brentano’s book On the Manifold Meaning of Being in Aristotle.
In 1907, the seventeen-year-old Heidegger asked: “If what-is is
predicated in manifold meanings, then what is its leading fundamental
meaning? What does being mean?” The question of being, unanswered at
that time, becomes the leading question of Being and Time twenty
years later. Surveying the long history of the meaning attributed to
“being,” Heidegger notes that in the philosophical tradition it has
generally been presupposed that being is at once the most universal
concept, the concept indefinable in terms of other concepts, and the
self-evident concept. In short, it is a concept that is mostly taken for
granted. However, Heidegger claims that even though we seem to
understand being, its meaning is still veiled in darkness. Therefore, we
need to restate the question of the meaning of being.
In accordance with the method of philosophy which he employs in his
fundamental treatise, before attempting to provide an answer to the
question of being in general, Heidegger sets out to answer the question
of the being of the particular kind of entity that is the human being,
which he calls Dasein.
The vivid phenomenological descriptions of Dasein’s being-in-the-world,
especially Dasein’s everydayness and resoluteness toward death, have
attracted many readers with interests related to existential philosophy,
theology, and literature. The basic concepts such as temporality,
understanding, historicity, repetition, and authentic or inauthentic
existence were carried over into and further explored in his later
works. Still, from the point of view of the quest for the meaning of
being, Being and Time was
a failure and remained unfinished. As Heidegger himself admitted in his
later essay, “Letter on Humanism” (1946), the third division of its
first part, entitled “Time and Being,” was held back “because thinking
failed in adequate saying of the turning and did not succeed with the help of the language of metaphysics.” The second part also remained unwritten.
“The turn” (Kehre)
that occurs in the 1930’s is the change in Heidegger’s thinking
mentioned above. The consequence of “the turn” is not the abandoning of
the leading question of Being and Time.
Heidegger stresses the continuity of his thought over the course of the
change. Nevertheless, as “everything is reversed,” even the question
concerning the meaning of Being is reformulated in Heidegger’s later
work. It becomes a question of the openness, that is, of the truth, of
being. Furthermore, since the openness of being refers to a situation
within history, the most important concept in the later Heidegger
becomes the history of being.
For a reader unacquainted with Heidegger’s thought, both the “question
of the meaning of being” and the expression “history of being” sound
strange. In the first place, such a reader may argue that when something
is said to be, there is nothing expressed which the world “Being” could
properly denote. Therefore, the word “being” is a meaningless term and
the Heideggerian quest for the meaning of being is in general a
misunderstanding. Secondly, the reader may also think that the being of
Heidegger is no more likely to have a history than the being of
Aristotle, so the “history of being” is a misunderstanding as well.
Nevertheless, Heidegger’s task is precisely to show that there is a
meaningful concept of being. “We understand the ‘is’ we use in
speaking,” he claims, “although we do not comprehend it conceptually.”
Therefore, Heidegger asks: Can being then be thought? We can think of
beings: a table, my desk, the pencil with which I am writing, the school
building, a heavy storm in the mountains . . . but being? If the being
whose meaning Heidegger seeks seems so elusive, almost like no-thing, it
is because it is not an entity. It is not something; it is not a being.
“Being is essentially different from a being, from beings.” The
“ontological difference,” the distinction between being (das Sein) and beings (das Seiende),
is fundamental for Heidegger. The forgetfulness of being that,
according to him, occurs in the course of Western philosophy amounts to
the oblivion of this distinction.
The conception of the history of being is of central importance in Heidegger’s thought. Already in Being and Time its
idea is foreshadowed as “the destruction of the history of ontology.”
In Heidegger’s later writings the story is considerably recast and
called the “history of being” (Seinsgeschichte).
The beginning of this story, as told by Heidegger especially in the
Nietzsche lectures, is the end, the completion of philosophy by its
dissolution into particular sciences and nihilism—questionlessness of
being, a dead end into which the West has run. Heidegger argues that the
question of being would still provide a stimulus to the research of
Plato and Aristotle, but it was precisely with them that the original
experience of being of the early Greeks was covered over. The fateful
event was followed by the gradual slipping away of the distinction
between being and beings. Described variously by different philosophers,
being was reduced to a being: to idea in Plato, substantia and actualitas in
Medieval philosophy, objectivity in modern philosophy, and will to
power in Nietzsche and contemporary thought. The task which the later
Heidegger sets before himself is then to make a way back into the
primordial beginning, so that the “dead end” can be replaced by a new
beginning. And since the primordial beginning of western thought lies in
ancient Greece, in order to solve the problems of contemporary
philosophy and reverse the course of modern history, Heidegger
ultimately turns for help to the Presocratics, the first western
thinkers.
5. Overcoming Metaphysics
For the later Heidegger, “western philosophy,” in which there occurs
forgetfulness of being, is synonymous with “the tradition of
metaphysics.” Metaphysics inquires about the being of beings, but in
such a way that the question of being as such is disregarded, and being
itself is obliterated. The Heideggerian “history of being” can thus be
seen as the history of metaphysics, which is the history of being’s
oblivion. However, looked at from another angle, metaphysics is also the
way of thinking that looks beyond beings toward their ground or basis.
Each metaphysics aims at the fundamentum absolutum, the ground of such a metaphysics which presents itself indubitably. In Descartes, for example, the fundamentum absolutum is attained through the “Cogito”
argument. Cartesian metaphysics is characterized by subjectivity
because it has its ground in the self-certain subject. Furthermore,
metaphysics is not merely the philosophy which asks the question of the
being of beings. At
the end of philosophy—i.e., in our present age where there occurs the
dissolution of philosophy into particular sciences—the sciences still
speak of the being of what-is as a whole. In the wider sense of this
term, metaphysics is thus, for Heidegger, any discipline which, whether
explicitly or not, provides an answer to the question of the being of
beings and of their ground. In medieval times such a discipline was
scholastic philosophy, which defined beings as entia creatum (created things) and provided them with their ground in ens perfectissimum (the
perfect being), God. Today the discipline is modern technology, through
which the contemporary human being establishes himself in the world by
working on it in the various modes of making and shaping. Technology
forms and controls the human position in today’s world. It masters and
dominates beings in various ways.
“In distinction from mastering beings, the thinking of thinkers is the
thinking of being.” Heidegger believes that early Greek thinking is not
yet metaphysics. Presocratic thinkers ask the question concerning the
being of beings, but in such a way that being itself is laid open. They
experience the being of beings as the presencing (Anwesen) of what is present (Anwesende).
Being as presencing means enduring in unconcealment, disclosing.
Throughout his later works Heidegger uses several words in order rightly
to convey this Greek experience. What-is, what is present, the
unconcealed, is “what appears from out of itself, in appearing shows
itself , and in this self-showing manifests.” It is the “emerging
arising, the unfolding that lingers.” He describes this experience with
the Greek words phusis (emerging dominance) and alêtheia (unconcealment). He
attempts to show that the early Greeks did not “objectify” beings (they
did not try to reduce them to an object for the thinking subject), but
they let them be as they were, as self-showing rising into
unconcealment. They experienced the phenomenality of
what is present, its radiant self-showing. The departure of Western
philosophical tradition from concern with what is present in presencing,
from this unique experience that astonished the Greeks, has had
profound theoretical and practical consequences.
According to Heidegger, the experience of what is present in presencing
signifies the true, unmediated experience of “the things themselves” (die Sache selbst).
We may recall that the call to “the things themselves” was included in
the Husserlian program of phenomenology. By means of phenomenological
description Husserl attempted to arrive at pure phenomena and to
describe beings just as they were given independently of any
presuppositions. For Heidegger, this attempt has, however, a serious
drawback. Like the tradition of modern philosophy preceding him, Husserl
stood at the ground of subjectivity. The transcendental subjectivity or
consciousness was for him “the sole absolute being.” It was the
presupposition that had not been accounted for in his program which
aimed to be presuppositionless. Consequently, in Heidegger’s view, the
Husserlian attempt to arrive at pure, unmediated phenomena fails.
Husserl’s phenomenology departs from the original phenomenality of
beings and represents them in terms of the thinking subject as their
presupposed ground. By contrast, Heidegger argues, for the Presocratics,
beings are grounded in being as presencing. Being, however, is not a
ground. To the early Greeks, being, unlimited in its dis-closure,
appears as an abyss, the source of thought and wonder. Being calls
everything into question, casts the human being out of any habitual
ground, and opens before him the mystery of existence.
The departure of western philosophical tradition from what is present in
presencing results in metaphysics. Heidegger believes that today’s
metaphysics, in the form of technology and the calculative thinking
related to it, has become so pervasive that there is no realm of life
that is not subject to its dominance. It imposes its
technological-scientific-industrial character on human beings, making it
the sole criterion of the human sojourn on earth. As it ultimately
degenerates into ideologies and worldviews, metaphysics provides an
answer to the question of the being of beings for contemporary men and
women, but skillfully removes from their lives the problem of their own
existence. Moreover, because its sway over contemporary human beings is
so powerful, metaphysics cannot be simply cast aside or rejected. Any
direct attempt to do so will only strengthen its hold. Metaphysics
cannot be rejected, canceled or denied, but it can be overcome by
demonstrating its nihilism. In Heidegger’s use of the term, “nihilism”
has a very specific meaning. It refers to the forgetfulness of being.
What remains unquestioned and forgotten in metaphysics is Being; hence,
it is nihilistic.
According to Heidegger, Western humankind in all its relations with
beings is sustained by metaphysics. Every age, every human epoch, no
matter however different they may be—
Greece after the Presocratics, Rome, the Middle Ages, modernity—has
asserted a metaphysics and, therefore, is placed in a specific
relationship to what-is as a whole. Metaphysics inquires about the being
of beings, but it reduces being to a being; it does not think of being
as being. Insofar as being itself is obliterated in it, metaphysics is
nihilism. The metaphysics of Plato is no less nihilistic than that of
Nietzsche. Consequently, Heidegger tries to demonstrate the nihilism of
metaphysics in his account of the history of being, which he considers
as the history of being’s oblivion. His attempt to overcome metaphysics
is not based on a common-sense positing of a different set of values or
the setting out of an alternative worldview, but rather is related to
his concept of history, the central theme of which is the repetition of
the possibilities for existence. This repetition consists in thinking
being back to the primordial beginning of the West—to the early Greek
experience of being as presencing—and repeating this beginning, so that
the Western world can begin anew.
6. From the First Beginning to the New Beginning
Many scholars perceive something unique in the Greek beginning of
philosophy. It is commonly acknowledged that Thales and his successors
asked generalized questions concerning what is as a whole, and proposed
general, rational answers which were no longer based on a theological
ground. However, Heidegger does not associate the unique beginning with
the alleged discovery of rationality and science. In fact, he claims
that both rationality and science are later developments, so that they
cannot apply to Presocratic thought. In his view, the Presocratics ask:
“What are beings as such as a whole?” and they answer: aletheia—unconcealment. They experience beings in their phenomenality: as what is present in presencing.
But the later thought which begins with Plato and Aristotle is unable
to keep up with the beginning. With Plato and Aristotle metaphysics
begins and the history of being’s oblivion originates.
The aim which the later Heidegger sets before himself is precisely to
return to the original experience of beings in being that stands at the
beginning of Western thought. This unmediated experience of beings in
their phenomenality can be variously described: what is present in presencing,
the unconcealment of what is present, the original disclosure of
beings. To repeat the primordial beginning more originally in its
originality means to bring us back to the Presocratic experiences, to
dis-close them, and to let them be as they originally are. But the
repetition is not for the sake of the Presocratics themselves.
Heidegger’s work is not a mere antiquarian, scholarly study of early
Greek thinking, nor is it an affirmation of the long lost Greek way of
life. It occurs within the perspective of nihilism and being’s
forgetfulness, both unknown to the Greeks, and has as a goal the future
possibilities for existence. It happens as the listening that opens
itself out to the words of the Presocratics from our contemporary age,
from the age of the world picture and representation, the world which is
marked by the domination of technology and the oblivion of being. In
the first beginning, the task of the Greeks was to ask the question
“What are beings?,” and hence to bring beings as such as a whole to the
first recognition and the most simple interpretation. In the end, the
task is to make questionable what at the end of a long tradition of
philosophy-metaphysics has been forgotten. The new beginning begins thus
with the question of being.
From Being and Time (1927)
where the question of the meaning of being is first developed, but
still expressed in the language of metaphysics, to “Time and Being”
(1962) where an attempt to think being without regard to metaphysics is
made, Heidegger goes full circle. Heidegger begins by asking about the
multiple meanings of being and ends up conceding its multiplicity and
acknowledging that there are multiple determinations or meanings of
being in which being discloses itself in history. Nevertheless, in
neither of these meanings does being give itself fully. “As it discloses
itself in beings, being withdraws.” There is an essential withdrawal of
being. Therefore, the truth of being is none of its particular
historical determinations—idea, substantia, actualitas,
objectivity or the will to power. The truth of being can be defined as
the openness, the free region which always out of sight provides the
space of play for the different determinations of being and human epochs
established in them. It is that which is before actual things and
grants them a possibility of manifestation as what is present, ens creatum, and objects.
The truth of being, its openness, is for Heidegger not something which
we can merely consider or think of. It is not our own production. It is
where we always come to stand. We find ourselves thrown in a
historically conditioned environment, in an epoch in which the decision
concerning the prevailing interpretation of the being of being is
already made for us. Yet, by asking the question of being, we can at
least attempt to free ourselves from our historical conditioning.
Heidegger’s program expressed in “The End of Philosophy and the Task of
Thinking” (1964) consists solely in the character of thinking which does
not attempt to dominate, but engages in disclosing and opening up what
shows itself, emerges, and is manifest. When Heidegger urges us to stand
in being, he does not merely ask us to acknowledge our own place in
being’s history, but to be future-oriented and see the future in a unity
with the past as having-been and the present. It means turning oneself
into being in its disclosing withdrawal.
7. From Philosophy to Political Theory
Heidegger never claimed that his philosophy was concerned with politics.
Nevertheless, there are certainly some political implications of his
thought. He perceives the metaphysical culture of the West as a
continuity. It begins with Plato and ends with modernity, and the
dominance of science and technology. He thus implies in the
post-modernist fashion that Nazism and the atom bomb, Auschwitz and
Hiroshima, have been something like the “fulfillment” of the tradition
of Western metaphysics and tries to distance himself from that
tradition. He turns to the Presocratics in order to retrieve a
pre-metaphysical mode of thought that would serve as a starting point
for a new beginning. However, his grand vision of the essential history
of the West and of western nihilism can be questioned. Modernity, whose
development involves not only a technological but also a social
revolution, which sets individuals loose from religious and ethnic
communities, from parishes and family bonds, and which affirms
materialistic values, can be regarded as a radical departure from
earlier classical and Christian traditions. Contrary to Heidegger’s
argument, rather than being a mere continuity, the “essential” history
of the West can then be seen as a history of radical transformations.
Christianity challenges the classical world, while assimilating some
aspects of it, and is in turn challenged by modernity. Modernity
overturns the ideas and values of the traditional (Christian and
classical) culture of the West, and, once it becomes global, leads to
the erosion of nonwestern traditional cultures.
Under the cover of immense speculative depth and rich ontological
vocabulary full of intricate wordplay (both which make his writings
extremely hard to follow) Heidegger expresses a simple political vision.
He is a revolutionary thinker who denies the traditional philosophical
division between theory and practice, and this is especially clear when
he boldly declares in his Introduction to Metaphysics that
“we have undertaken the great and lengthy task of demolishing a world
that has grown old and of building it truly anew”. He wants to overturn
the traditional culture of the West and build it anew on the basis of
earlier traditions in the name of being. Like other thinkers of
modernity, he adopts a Eurocentric perspective and sees the revival of
German society as a condition for the revival of Europe (or the West),
and that of Europe as a condition for the revival of for the whole
world; like them, while rejecting God as an end, he attempts to set up
fabricated ends for human beings. Ultimately, in the famous interview
with Der Spiegel,
he expresses his disillusionment with his project and says: “Philosophy
will not be able to bring about a direct change of the present state of
the world . . . The greatness of what is to be thought is too great.”
Like being, which he describes as “disclosing self-concealing,” after
making a disclosure he withdraws; after stirring up a revolution, he
leaves all its problems to others. He says: “only a God can still save
us,” but the God for whom, in the absence of philosophical thought, he
now looks is clearly not that of the Christians or of any contemporary
religion.
In the Spiegel interview
Heidegger tells us that in order to begin anew, we need to go to the
“age-old” (i.e., pre-classical and pre-metaphysical) traditions of
thought. He invokes the concept of the ancient polis.
Yet, since he does not want to concern himself with the question of
ethics (beyond saying in the “Letter of Humanism” that the word “ethics appeared
for the first time in the school of Plato” and thus implying that
ethics does not think the truth of being and is nihilistic), he does not
consider the fact that even in pre-Platonic and pre-Socratic times a
Greek polis was an ethical community, in which moral questions were raised and discussed. The Iliad and Odyssey of
Homer, the poems of Hesiod, and the tragedies of Sophocles, as well as
the other ancient Greek texts, including the monumental political work
of Thucydides, the History of the Peloponnesian War,express
concerns with ethical behavior at both the individual and community
levels. Furthermore, the strength of Western civilization, insofar as
its roots can be traced to ancient Greece, is that from its beginning it
was based on rationality, understood as free debate, and the
affirmation of fundamental moral values. Whenever it turned to
irrationality and moral relativism, as in Nazism and Communism, that
civilization was in decline. Therefore, Heidegger is likely to be
mistaken in his diagnosis of the ills of the contemporary society, and
his solution to those ills seems to be wrong. Asking the question of
being (and, drawing our attention to this question is certainly his
significant contribution) is an important addition to, but never a
replacement for asking moral questions in the spirit of rationality and
freedom.
Heidegger claims that the human being as Da-sein can be understood as the “there” (Da) which being (Sein)
requires in order to disclose itself. The human being is the unique
being whose being has the character of openness toward Being. But men
and women can also turn away from being, forget their true selves, and
thus deprive themselves of their humanity. This is, in Heidegger’s view,
the situation of contemporary humans, who have replaced authentic
questioning concerning their existence with ready-made answers served up
by ideologies, the mass media, and overwhelming technology.
Consequently, Heidegger attempts to bring today’s men and women back to
the question of being. At the beginning of the tradition of Western
philosophy, the human being was defined as animal rationale,
the animal endowed with reason. Since then, reason has become an
absolute value which through education brings about a gradual
transformation of all spheres of human life. It is not more reason in
the modern sense of calculative thinking, Heidegger believes, that we
need today, but more openness toward and more reflection on that which
is nearest to us—being.
8. Heidegger's Collected Works
Heidegger’s earlier publications and transcripts of his lectures are being brought out in Gesamtausgabe, the complete edition of his works. The Gesamtausgabe,
which is not yet complete and projected to fill about one hundred
volumes, is published by Vittorio Klostermann, Frankfurt am Main. The
series consists of four divisions: (I) Published Writings 1910-1976;
(II) Lectures from Marburg and Freiburg, 1919-1944; (III) Private
Monographs and
Lectures, 1919-1967; (IV) Notes and Fragments. Below there is a list of
the collected works of Martin Heidegger. English translations and
publishers are cited with each work translated into English.
a. Published Writings, 1910-1976
- Frühe Schriften (1912-16).
- Sein und Zeit (1927). Translated as Being and Time by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978).
- Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929). Translated as Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, by Richard Taft (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997).
- Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung (1936-68). Translated as Elucidations of Hölderlin's Poetry, by Keith Hoeller (Amherst, New York: Humanity Books, 2000).
-
Holzwege (1935-46).
- “Der Ursprung der Kunstwerkes.” Translated as “The Origin of the Work of Art,” by Albert Hofstadter, in Poetry, Language, Thought (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), and in Basic Writings (New York: Harper & Row, 1977, 1993).
- “Die Zeit des Weltbildes.” Translated as “The Age of the World Picture” by William Lovitt in The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays (NewYork: Harper & Row, 1977).
- “Hegels Begriff der Erfahrung.”
- “Nietzsches Wort 'Gott ist tot'.” Translated as “The Word of Nietzsche: ‘God Is Dead’” by William Lovitt in The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
- “Wozu Dichter?.” Translated as “What Are Poets For?” by Albert Hofstadter, in Poetry, Language, Thought.
- “Der Spruch der Anaximander.” Translated as “The Anaximander Fragment” by David F. Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi in Early Greek Thinking (New York: Harper & Row, 1975).
- Vol. I, Nietzsche I (1936-39). Translated as Nietzsche I: The Will to Power as Art by David F. Krell (New York: Harper & Row, 1979)
- Vol. II, Nietzsche II (1939-46). Translated as “The Eternal Recurrence of the Same” by David F. Krell in Nietzsche II: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same (New York, Harper & Row, 1984).
-
Vorträge und Aufsätze (1936-53).
- “Die Frage nach der Technik.” Translated as “The Question Concerning Technology” by William Lovitt in The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
- “Wissenschaft und Besinnung.” Translated as “Science and Reflection” by William Lovitt in The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
- “Überwindung der Metaphysik.” Translated as “Overcoming Metaphysics” by Joan Stambaugh in The End of Philosophy (New York: Harper & Row, 1973).
- “Wer ist Nietzsches Zarathustra.” Translated as “Who is Nietzsche’s Zarathustra?” by David F. Krell in Nietzsche II:The Eternal Recurrence of the Same.
- “Bauen Wohnen Denken.” Translated as “Building Dwelling Thinking.”
- “Das Ding.” Translated as “The Thing” by Albert Hofstadter, in Poetry, Language, Thought.
- “...dichterisch wohnet der Mensch...” Translated as “...Poetically Man Dwells...” by Albert Hofstadter, in Poetry, Language, Thought.
- “Logos.” Translated as “Logos (Heraclitus, Fragment B 50)” by David F. Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi in Early Greek Thinking.
- “Moira.” Translated as “Moira (Parmenides VIII, 34-41)” by David F. Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi in Early Greek Thinking.
- “Aletheia.” Translated as “Aletheia (Heraclius, Fragment B 16)” by David F. Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi in Early Greek Thinking.
- Was heisst Denken? (1951-52). Translated as What Is Called Thinking? by Fred D. Wieck and J. Glenn Gray (New York: Harper & Row, 1968).
-
Wegmarken (1919-58). Translated as Pathmarks. Edited by William McNeill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
- Contains: “Comments on Karl Jaspers’ Psychology of Worldviews” (1919/21), “Phenomenology and Theology” (1927), “From the Last Marburg Lecture Course” (1928), “What is Metaphysics?” (1929), “On the Essence of Ground” (1929), “On the Essence of Truth” (1930), “Plato’s Doctrine of Truth” (1931-1932, 1940), “On the Essence and Concept in Aristotle's Physics B 1” (1939), “Postscript to ‘What is Metaphysics?’” (1943); “Letter on Humanism” (1946), “Introduction to ‘What is Metaphysics?’” (1949), “On the Question of Being” (1955), “Hegel and the Greeks” (1958), “Kant’s Thesis About Being” (1961).
- Der Satz vom Grund (1955-56). Translated as The Principle of Reason by Reginald Lilly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991).
- Identität und Differenz (1955-57). Translated as Identity and Difference by Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1969).
- Unterwegs zur Sprache (1950-59). Translated as On the Way to Language by Peter D. Hertz (New York: Harper & Row, 1971).
- Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens (1910-76).
- Zur Sache des Denkens (1962-64). Translated as On Time and Being by Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1972). Contains: “Time and Being,” “The End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking,” and “My Way to Phenomenology.”
- Seminare (1951-73).
- Reden und andere Zeugnisse eines Lebensweges (1910-1976).
b. Lectures from Marburg and Freiburg, 1919-1944
- Der Beginn der neuzeitlichen Philosophie (winter semester, 1923-1924).
- Aristoteles: Rhetorik (summer semester, 1924).
- Platon: Sophistes (winter semester, 1924-1925). Translated as Plato's Sophist by Richard Rojcewicz and Andre Schuwer (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1997).
- Prolegomena zur Geschite des Zeitbegriffs (summer semester, 1925). Translated as History of the Concept of Time by Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985).
- Logik: Die frage nach der Wahrheit (winter semester 1925-1926).
- Grundbegriffe der antiken Philosophie (summer semester 1926).
- Geschichte der Philosophie von Thomas v. Aquin bis Kant (winter semester 1926-1927).
- Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (summer semester 1927). Translated as The Basic Problems of Phenomonology by Albert Hofstadter (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982).
- Phänomenologie Interpretation von Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft (winter semester 1927-1928). Translated as Phenomenological Interpretations of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997).
- Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz (summer semester, 1928). Translated as The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic by Michael Heim (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984).
- Einleitung in die Philosophie (winter semester 1928-1929).
- Der Deutsche Idealismus (Fichte, Hegel, Schelling) und die philosophische Problemlage der Gegenwart(summer semester, 1929).
- Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik: Welt-Endlichkeit-Einsamkeit (winter semester, 1929-1930). Translated as The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics by William McNeill and Nicholas Walker (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995).
- Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit. Einleitung in die Philosophie (summer semester, 1930).
- Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes (winter semester, 1930-1931). Translated as Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988).
- Aristoteles: Metaphysik IX (summer semester, 1931). Translated as Aristotle's Metaphysics Theta 1-3 On the Essence and Actuality of Force by Walter Brogan and Peter Warnek (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995).
- Vom Wesen der Wahrheit. Zu Platons Höhlengleichnis und Theätet (winter semester, 1931-1932).
- Der Anfang der abendländischen Philosophie (Anaximander und Parmenides) (summer semester, 1932).
- Sein und Wahrheit (winter semester, 1933-1934).
- Logik als die Frage nach dem Wesen der Sprache (summer semester, 1934).
- Hölderlins Hymnen "Germanien" und "Der Rhein" (winter semester, 1934-1935).
- Einführung in die Metaphysik (summer semester, 1935). Translated as An Introduction to Metaphysics by Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2000).
- Die Frage nach dem Ding. Zu Kants Lehre von den transzendentalen Grundsätzen. (winter semester, 1935-1936). Translated as What Is a Thing by W. B. Barton, Jr. and Vera Deutsch, (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1967).
- Schelling: Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit (1809) (summer semester, 1936). Translated as Schelling's Treatise on the Essence of Human Freedom by Joan Stambaugh, (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1984).
- Nietzsche: Der Wille zur Macht als Kunst (winter semester, 1936-1937). Translated as Nietzsche I: The Will to Power as Art by David F. Krell (New York, Harper & Row, 1979).
- Nietzsches Metaphysische Grundstellung im abendländischen Denken: Die ewige Wiederkehr des Gleichen(summer semester, 1937). Translated as “The Eternal Recurrence of the Same” in Nietzsche II: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same by David F. Krell (New York: Harper & Row, 1984).
- Grundfragen der Philosophie. Ausgewählte "Probleme" der "Logik" (winter semester, 1937-1938). Translated as Basic Questions of Philosophy by Albert Hofstadter (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982).
- Nietzsches II. Unzeitgemässe Betrachtung (winter semester, 1938-1939).
- Nietzsches Lehre vom Willen zur Macht als Erkenntnis (summer semester, 1939). Translated as "The Will to Power as Knowledge" in Nietzsche III: The Will to Power as Knowledge and Metaphysics by Joan Stambaugh (New York, Harper & Row, 1987).
- Nietzsche: Der europäische Nihilismus (second trimester, 1940).
- Die Metaphysik des deutschen Idealismus. Zur erneuten auslegung von Schelling: Philosophische untersuchungen ueber das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit und die damit zusammenhaengenden Gegenstaende (1809) (first trimester, 1941).
- Nietzsches Metaphysik (1941-2). Einleitung in die Philosopie - Denken und Dichten (1944-5).
- Grundbegriffe (summer semester, 1941). Translated as Basic Concepts by Gary Aylesworth (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993).
- Hölderlins Hymne "Andenken" (winter semester, 1941-1942).
- Hölderlins Hymne "Der Ister" (summer semester, 1942). Translated as Hölderlin's Hymn "The Ister" by William McNeill and Julia Davis (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996).
- Parmenides (winter semester, 1942-1943). Translated as Parmenides by Andre Schuwer and Richard Rojcewicz (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1992).
- Heraklit. 1. Der Anfang des abendländischen Denkens (Heraklit). (summer semester, 1943); 2. Logik. Heraklits Lehre vom Logos (summer semester, 1944).
- Zur Bestimmung der Philosophie (1919).
- Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (winter semester, 1919-1920).
- Phaenomenologie der Anschauung und des Ausdrucks. Theorie der philosophischen Begriffsbildung (summer semester, 1920).
- Phänomenologie des religiösen Lebens (summer semester, 1921).
- Phänomenologische Interpretationen zu Aristoteles: Einführung in die phänomeno-logische Forschung(winter semester, 1921-1922).
- Phänomenologische Interpretationen ausgewählter Abhandlungen des Aristoteles zur Ontologie und Logik. (summer semester, 1922).
- Ontologie: Hermeneutik der Faktizität (summer semester, 1923). Translated as Ontology: The Hermeneutics of Facticity by John va Buren (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999).
c. Private Monographs and Lectures, 1919-1967
- Der Begriff der Zeit (1924). Translated as The Concept of Time by William McNeill, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).
- Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis) (1936-1938). Translated as Contributions to Philosophy: (From Enowning) by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999).
- Besinnung.
- Metaphysik und Nihilismus. Die Überwindung derMetaphysik. Das Wesen des Nihilismus.
- Hegel. Die Negativität. Eine Auseinandersetzung mit Hegel aus dem Ansatz in der Negativität (1938-1939, 1941). 2 Erläuterung der "Einleitung" zu Hegels "Phänomenologie des Geistes" (1942).
- Die Geschichte des Seyns (1938-1940).
- Das Ereignis (1941)
- Wahrheitsfrage als Vorfrage. Die Aletheia: Die Erinnerung in den ersten Anfang; Entmachtung der Ousis (1937).
- Zu Hölderlin - Griechenlandreisen.
- Feldweg-Gespräche. (1944-1945)
- Bremer und Freiburger Vortraege.
- Vorträge Vom Wesen der Wahrheit Freiburg lecture (1930). Der Ursprung der Kunstwerkes (1935).
- Gedachtes.
- Anmerkungen zu "Vom Wesen des Grundes" (1936). Eine Auseinandersetzung mit "Sein und Zeit" (1936). Laufende Anmerkungen zu Sein und Zeit (1936).
- Marburger Übungen. Auslegungen der Aristotelischen "physik".
- Leibniz-Übungen.
d. Notes and Fragments
- Vom Wesen der Sprache
- Übungen SS 1937. Neitzsches metaphysische Grundstellung. Sein und Schein (1937)
- Einübung in das Denken. Die metaphysischen Grundstellungen des abendländischen Denkens. Die Bedrohung der Wissenschaft.
- Überlegungen II-VI.
- Überlegungen VII-XI.
- Überlegungen XII-XV.
No comments:
Post a Comment